Journal List > Kosin Med J > v.28(2) > 1057014

Kim: Epidemiology and Causation

Abstract

In medicine and public health areas, it is essential for researchers and clinicians to investigate causal relationships dealing with the terms of cause, causation and causality. In treating a patient, the treatment will be given based on the assumption that that treatment will cause an improvement or cure of the patient. For diagnosis, we need a causation concept to associate diseases with etiologic factors such as genetic, environmental, occupational and other components. The prevention and intervention of a disease involve the selecting process of probable causal factors too.
The causal problem is one of main issues in philosophy since ancient Greek. Aristotle theorized material, formal, efficient, and formal causes. Francis Bacon and Descartes mainly used induction and deduction, respectively. Hume denied the capacity of inductive methodologies to find truth. Among philosophers of science, the debates whether we can find objective truth or not will be continued. This causation can be two subsets, ontological and epistemological (or methodological). Traditional philosophical approaches mainly focus on ontological problems, such as what is causation?; are there causal laws? In general, scientific or epidemiological approaches are dealing with the epistemological dimension, i.e, causation criteria; test for a causal hypothesis.
For clinicians and researchers in medical and public health, it would be a good chance to review and re-think the notions of cause, causation and causality. Also there will be helpful understanding of more detail informations about the methodology such as causal inference, Hill’s criteria and Rothman’s causal pie model.

REFERENCES

1.Elwood JM. Critical appraisal of epidemiological studies and clinical trials. 3rd ed.New York: Oxford University Press;2007.
2.Mun JS., Choi SD., Jo SG. The historical-critical study of the important epistemological interpretations of the status of the principle of causality. The New Korean Philosophical Association. J NKPA. 1998. 15:113–35.
3.Rothman KJ. Inferring causal connections –habit, faith or logic? Rothman KJ, editor. editor.Causal Inferences. Chestnut Hill (MA): Epidemiology Resources Inc;1988. p.3–12.
4.Rothman KJ. What is causation? In: Epidemiology: an introduction. 2nd ed.New York: Oxford University Press;2012. p. 23–37.
5.Choi HC. Hume's causation conception and scientific explanation. Philosophical Studies. 2006. 20:67–97.
6.Yan SR. A probablistic analysis of causation. Philosophy. 1990. 34:171–196.
7.Jang DI. Kuhn and Popper, Science has something special. Gimmyoung Publishers. 2008.
8.Yoon SK., Lee SY. A study on the evolution of the philosophy of science. J Soc Sci. 1998. 9:189–213.
9.Lee YC. Science and truth: Popper vs. Wittenstein-Davidson. Philosophy. 1993. 39:303–24.
10.Shin JS. Science and philosophy of science. Science Philosophy and Culture. 1995. 15:79–98.
11.Bunge M. Causality and modern science. 3rd edition.New York: Dover Publication;1979.
12.Broadbent A. Conceptual and methodological issues in epidemiology: an overview. Prev Med. 2011. 53:215–6.
crossref
13.Hill AB. Observation and experiment. N Engl J Med. 1953. 248:995–1001.
crossref
14.Greenland S. Evolution of epidemiologic ideas: annotated readings on concepts and methods. 1st ed.Newton Lower Falls (MA): Epidemiology Resources Inc;1987.
15.Parascandola M., Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001. 55:905–12.
crossref
16.Kundi M. Causality and the interpretation of epidemiologic evidence. Environ Health Perspect. 2006. 114:969–74.
crossref
17.Hill AB. The environment and disease: association or causation? Proc R Soc Med. 1965. 58:295–300.
crossref
18.Lagiou P., Trichopoulos D., Adami HO. Concept in cancer epidemiology and etiology. Adami HO, Hunter D, Trichopoulos D, editors. editors.Textbook of Cancer Epidemiology. 2nd ed.New York: Oxford University Press;2008. p. 127–54.
19.Weed DL. Causal criteria and Popperian refutation. Rothman KJ, editor. editor.Causal Inferences. Chestnut Hill (MA): Epidemiology Resources Inc;1988. p.15–32.
20.Thygesen LC., Andersen GS., Andersen H. A philosophical analysis of the Hill criteria. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2005. 59:512–6.
crossref
21.Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976. 104:587–92.
crossref
22.Lee WC. Completion potentials of sufficient component causes. Epidemiology. 2012. 23:446–53.
crossref
23.Parascandola M. Causes, risks, and probabilities: probabilistic concepts of causation in chronic disease epidemiology. Prev Med. 2011. 53:232–4.
crossref
24.Olsen J. What characterises a useful concept of causation in epidemiology? J Epidemiol Community Health. 2003. 57:86–8.
crossref
25.Olsen J., Christensen K., Murray J., Ekbom A. An introduction to epidemiology for health professionals. 1st ed.New York: Springer;2010.
26.Rothman KJ., Greenland S., Poole C., Lash TL. Causation and causal inference. In: Rothman KJ, Lash TL, Greenland S, editors. Modern epidemiology. 3rd ed. Philadelphia: 2012. p.5–31.
27.Rothman KJ. Epidemiology: an introduction. 2nd ed.New York: Oxford University Press;2012.
28.Higginson J. Proportion of cancer due to occupation. Prev Med. 1980. 9:180–8.
29.Bernstein DI., Bernsten IL., Chan-Yeung M., Malo J. Definition and classification of asthma in the workplace. In: Bernstein DI, Chan-Yeung M, Malo J, Bernsten IL, editors. Asthma in the Workplace. 3rd ed. New York: 2006. p.1–8.

Fig. 1.
(A) A necessary cause, (B) A sufficient cause, (C) A necessary and sufficient cause, (D) Most of causes.
kmj-28-87f1.tif
Fig. 2.
Concept Diagram of Causal pie model.
kmj-28-87f2.tif
Fig. 3.
Depiction of the constellation of component causes that constitute a sufficient cause, and U represents all of the other unspecified event, conditions.
kmj-28-87f3.tif
Fig. 4.
A causal pie model for the oral cancer.
kmj-28-87f4.tif
Table 1.
Definitions of causation and their criticism from the epidemiological literature
Definition Main criticism
A cause is something that produces or create an effect. Tautological because “production” and “creation” synonyms of “causation”
A cause is a condition without which the effect cannot occur. Only few diseases could then have a cause
A cause is a condition with which the effect must occur. Again, few diseases could then have a cause
A cause is made up of several components, no single one of which is sufficient of its own, which taken together must led to the effect. Introduces unnecessary complexity in cases of simple dose response and in cases of interaction between components
A cause is a condition that increases the probability of occurrence of the effect. Dose not distinguish between an association and a “cause”c
A cause is a condition that, if present, makes a difference in (the probability of) the outcome. Is, in the strict sense, unprovable because there is only one world and one cannot observe it twice-once with and once without the condition
Table 2.
Hill‘s criteria and their problems
Criterion Problems of Criterion
1. Strength Strength depends on the prevalence of other causes; it is not a biologic characteristic and can be confounded.
2. Consistency Causal relations have exceptions that are understood best with hindsight.
3. Specificity A cause can have many effects.
4. Temporality It may be difficult to establish the temporal sequence between cause and effect.
5. Biologic gradient It can be confounded; threshold phenomena would not show a progressive relation.
6. Plausibility Too subjective
7. Coherence How does it differ from consistency or plausibility?
8. Experimental evidence Not always available
9. Analogy Analogies abound.
TOOLS
Similar articles